Lincoln
Lincoln reflected on the problem that ambition poses for democratic
government and for the rule of law in a speech that he gave to Young
Men's Lyceum in Springfield, Illinois, quite early in his political
career in 1838. In the quotation from that speech which introduces
this unit Lincoln contrasts those of ordinary ambition, who serve
their country by aspiring to its political offices such as the Presidency,
with those of superior political and/or military talent and of boundless
ambition to match. The classic examples are those mentioned by Lincoln:
world-conquerors such as Alexander, Caesar, and Napoleon, who changed
the course of history. One of the purposes of his speech is to warn
about the dangers of such individuals to established governments.
This unit discusses what moves ambitious men, in what ways they
serve their country and themselves, as well as what forms ambition
takes in different political settings. What limits do ambitious
individuals encounter, and what limits should they encounter? And
in what ways is greatness manifest? The talent for war is never
sufficient nor always even necessary for political greatness. Whereas
those men of boundless ambition whom Lincoln mentions are famous
for establishing anti-democratic regimes, Lincoln's own example
proves that this is not always the case. Democratic greatness may
be of a different kind altogether. However, it remains to be seen
whether democracy's limitation of the claims of the great can be
justified, and whether a democratic government that makes honorable
use of the great is possible.
Lincoln's speech "On the Perpetuation of our Political Institutions,"
often referred to as "the Lyceum Speech," is famous for
its seemingly self-prophetic line about a great man who will thirst
for the distinction of political rule, even at the "expense
of emancipating slaves, or enslaving freemen." But since Lincoln
presents this great man as one who will seize power and destroy
democratic government, it is clear that the emancipator he warns
against would have been a man who combined the qualities and aims
of a Napoleon and a John Brown. Such a man would have been rather
unlike Lincoln, and would have freed slaves for rather different
motives.
The speech elucidates the question that would dominate Lincoln's
entire career: whether a nation "dedicated to the proposition
that all men are created equal," could "long endure,"
and particularly whether it could resist threats to its existence
that came, not from foreign nations, but from within. Was government
of, by, and for the people simply a noble but overly optimistic
experiment that would eventually fail?
While in this speech Lincoln pits the desire of truly great persons
for political preeminence against the preservation of liberty,
a study of Lincoln's own life shows us a man of abundant talents
achieving the heights of greatness precisely because of his unwavering
dedication to the preservation of liberty. This speech
reveals, however, that Lincoln did not understand democracy as simple
rule of the majority. A mob, after all, is often a kind of direct
majority rule. Lincoln warns against the danger of mob rule (and
disrespect for law, which mob rule presumes) as he does against
the dangers of ambition. Lincoln is not dedicated to the proposition
that the majority always rules, but to the proposition that all
men are created equal, which means all persons should be equally
protected by laws, or that they should enjoy certain rights, such
as a right to a fair trial.
Lincoln illustrates the dangers posed to "The Perpetuation
of our Political Institutions" by the increasing incidents
of mob rule in the America of his day. Our task–his own task–he
implies is to eliminate the injustices that are protected by the
law without undermining law itself. It is this task–not that
of world conquerors–that calls for "towering genius."
Jefferson
Thomas Jefferson, corresponding with John Adams in 1813, defended
democracy precisely because it allowed the best individuals to rise
to positions of preeminence. The "natural aristocracy,"
far from threatening democratic government, was its greatest blessing
as well as its strongest justification. Eliminating the laws and
customs that supported permanent social classes, democracy opened
offices to the most qualified, giving the best individuals, regardless
of class, the opportunity to be elected to the positions of power.
Jefferson understood, however, the importance of education to the
character of a self-governing people, especially to "rais[ing]
the mass of people to the high ground of moral respectability"
necessary to orderly government and to election of the "veritable
aristoi" in free elections.
Tocqueville
Alexis de Tocqueville, a French aristocrat who toured the United
States in the 1830s and wrote Democracy in America, was
less sanguine about the potential of democracy to give rise to outstanding
individuals. In our selection, he points out the leveling effect
of the principle of equality both on thought and on action. When
all are thought equal, and conventional ranks and classes are given
no special authority, each individual is freed to think for himself.
But, given the principle of equality, his own thoughts have no more
worth that anyone else's. The opinion of the majority, or public
opinion, has a moral worth it would not have in more aristocratic
societies. In Tocqueville's analysis, the same condition that "lead[s]
the mind of every individual to untried thoughts," paradoxically
"induc[es] him to freely give up thinking at all." Equality
has its effect on human action and ambition as well, opening up
all fields of endeavor to everyone, but restraining by the same
token what any one individual can achieve. Thus Tocqueville finds
in America many ambitious people, but few of lofty ambition. Like
Lincoln and Jefferson, although with a different analysis of the
dangers, Tocqueville thought that democracy could not be taken for
granted, but required efforts to protect it, and even to educate
or refine the principles on which it was based.
Rousseau
Concern for the effects of society on the character of human beings
is not limited to democratic social conditions. In the 18th century,
Jean-Jacques Rousseau objected to the traditional understanding
derived from Aristotle that human beings are social or political
by nature, realizing their potentials and achieving happiness through
associating with others in political communities. Instead, Rousseau
argued that society corrupts human beings, by leading them to develop
artificial needs and desires. Losing their natural freedom and independence,
"social" beings become dependent on others to satisfy
their desires. In his major work on education, The Emile,
Rousseau contrasts a natural and healthy self-love (amour de
soi), by which we are concerned "only with ourselves"
and which satisfies our true needs, with the selfishness (amour-propre)
that develops as we grow up in society, which arises when we learn
to compare ourselves with others. This selfishness is the source
of pride and vanity, competition, envy, and all the irascible passions
that cause our unhappiness. Rousseau proposes the importance of
pity or compassion, which is based on our common weakness and suffering,
as a way of countering the selfishness that is unavoidable for social
beings. His proposal for an education in compassion suggests a quite
different defense of equality than we find in Jefferson, and while
Rousseau would agree with Lincoln and Tocqueville concerning the
dangers of relying on the opinions of society, his model for resisting
those opinions is a "democratic" individual of a different
sort.
Aristotle
Perhaps the most notable description of a proper self-regard in
Western literature, however, is found in Aristotle's Nicomachean
Ethics, in his description of the virtues, and of magnanimity
in particular. For Aristotle, the virtues that good human beings
exercise–from the moral virtues of courage, moderation, and
justice, to the intellectual virtues of prudence and wisdom–are
the major constituents of human happiness. Although the exercise
of the virtues generally involve us with other human beings–to
whom we are just in our actions or with whom we are courageous in
war–their exercise is the fulfillment of our natures as human
beings and thus the cause of our happiness. The individual with
proper regard for himself will therefore be virtuous in society
and in his relations with others. Aristotle's virtuous individual
is less dependent than Rousseau's "selfish" one, but more
social or political than Rousseau's "self-loving" one.
The virtue of magnanimity, literally "greatness of soul,"
however, poses special problems for the relation between the virtuous
individual and society. The magnanimous individual as Aristotle
defines him "is worthy of the greatest things and claims that
he is so." Out of self-regard, he does not deign to compete
with less deserving individuals, and prefers to give than to receive,
not out of duty, and surely not of compassion, but because it manifests
his independence and greatness. Holding back from action, except
when "a great work is at stake," he is "a person
of few deeds, but of great and notable ones." It is not clear,
however, what he does when there are no great and notable deeds
to perform, or whether his sense of his own worth offers him a strong
enough link to other human beings and the community they share.
In discussing magnanimity, Aristotle shows a possible conflict between
human greatness and society, or between virtuous self-regard and
the common good of all.
The second part of this unit examines several ambitious individuals:
Shakespeare's Coriolanus and Henry V, General Patton, Willie Stark
(of All the King's Men), and, finally, the ambitions of
Crash Davis and Ebby Calvin LaLoosh in the baseball world of Bull
Durham. We will see different kinds of ambition, the paths
ambition takes, the selfishness or self-regard that underlies ambition,
and the relation between ambitious individuals and other human beings.
Coriolanus
Caius Martius, who wins the name Coriolanus through
a military victory, is an exemplar of Roman military virtue who
unabashedly regards himself as superior to other men. Militarily,
he undoubtedly is superior, but he excels in other ways as well.
He is frank and honest even when it is costly to be so, and refuses
to give or receive any form of flattery. He can deliver rousing
speeches, and can convincingly expound the principles of the patrician-led
republican government, which he holds to firmly. Overall, he seems
naturally fit to lead Rome.
Rome, however, is undergoing a political struggle between its two
classes of society, the patricians (nobles) and the plebeians (the
common people), which is changing the nature of the regime. At the
beginning of Shakespeare's play, the plebeians revolt against the
patrician class, who rule Rome. To quell the rebellion, the Senate,
the institution through which the patricians rule, establishes the
office of the tribunes to represent the interests of the plebeians
and to give voice to their concerns. Now any man who desires to
attain the leadership positions, which are reserved for the best
of the patricians, must court the good will of the plebeians. Coriolanus,
who openly regards the plebeians as cowardly in war and fickle in
political matters, and who denounces their recently won rights,
is incapable of this. He will not hide his opinions nor soften his
harsh manners for his own gain, nor for Rome's well-being. He demands
to be taken as he is. The plebeians are willing to at first, since
after all he is a war hero who has defended their country, and so
they ratify the Senate's choice of him for consul, which is the
public office of greatest power and honor. But when the tribunes
remind them of Coriolanus' manner toward them and generally stir
up their anger, they revoke their vote and denounce him as an enemy.
As a result, the tensions between the plebeians and patricians threaten
to erupt in open civil war. Many of the wiser patricians counsel
compromise, but the indignant Coriolanus insists upon unapologetic
adherence to what he regards as Rome's highest political principle,
rule by the best, even as it threatens to bring about the worst
political result.
What, then, can Rome do with Coriolanus? This, and the shocking
results that follow, the reader will discover. The play is indeed
quite exciting, with many scenes occurring in the midst of battles
or angry mobs. Some version of Shakespeare's story actually happened,
as it is based upon Plutarch's account in his Lives of Noble
Grecians and Romans.
The play simultaneously gives expression to and shows the shortcomings
of one of the most potent political ideas humanity has entertained
over the ages, that the best ought to rule. If we simply derive
a moral of "pride begets a fall," the play will seem to
be a rather pointless fuss over a rather colorless snob. If, however,
we see that there is a strong case to be made for the patrician
side generally, and for Coriolanus specifically, we can begin to
grasp the seriousness of the two main conflicts in the play, between
democratic and aristocratic values, on one hand, and between political
compromise and personal integrity, on the other.
Henry V
The Macedonians had their Alexander, the Romans their Caesar,
and in Shakespeare's day, the English had their own conquering warrior
to hark back to, Henry V. Prior to his sudden death due to disease,
at age 34, he had conquered much of northern France, won incredible
concessions from the French in the Treaty of Troye, and due to these
successes and his marriage to the French king's daughter arranged
in that treaty, looked as if he might go on to establish a dual
kingdom of France and England.
As a foil to Coriolanus, Shakespeare's Henry V is particularly
interesting, because while he has more power over the common people
and less political need to cater to their desires, he exhibits warm
affection toward them, and in one speech seems to espouse a belief
in a basic human equality. Indeed, prior to his becoming king, he
was known to spend much time carousing in the taverns and even thieving
with lowly tavern types, as Shakespeare reminds his audience at
the beginning of the play. Since he did this in part to win esteem
through a most noticeable "reformation" (Henry IV,
Part I, Act I, Sc. 2, 165-185), his real attitude toward the
common people is better seen in Henry V, where he inspires
his soldiers, many of whom are commoners, and meditates on the fact
that he may be leading them to their deaths. Although Henry claims
that "if it be a sin to covet honor, I am the most offending
soul alive," his stirring rhetoric promotes unity between the
various classes in his army and refers to all of them, himself included,
as "a band of brothers."
Kenneth Branagh used this play to create one of the finest and
most exciting film adaptations of Shakespeare. Branagh's screenplay
(available on-line) judiciously edits the play for the screen. Students
can therefore obtain a good sense of the play from the movie and
the excerpts of the play provided here. For those following the
film, we have bracketed certain sections of the play that Branagh
omitted from the film, which give a fuller picture of Shakespeare's
purpose.
Patton
The blurbs say: "Maverick General! Super Patriot and Super
Rebel!" And indeed, for many, Patton will remain an icon, like
John Wayne, of rugged American individualism. But there is much
more to the movie, and the man, than that. Indeed, to leave it at
that would be to miss the point. Unlike Coriolanus, General Patton
knew how to put on an act when it was in his interests to do so,
and his main act was pushing his own feisty personality over the
top, so that his soldiers would be inspired to be brave, aggressive,
and confident. Reporters dubbed him "old blood and guts"
for the gory details and exhortations to bravery he used in his
speeches. Like Coriolanus, Patton's reputation for fighting spirit
and bravery was based upon deeds. Moreover, for battlefield strategy
he had no peer in the allied armies.
Unlike Henry V, a king striving to obtain another kingdom, or Coriolanus,
a patrician expecting to become consul, this warrior was a servant
of a democracy. Still, Patton was something of an aristocrat. His
wealthy family was known for its forebears' prominence in confederate
military service, and he married into an even more upper-crust family
from Boston. He maintained horses, competed in polo and steeplechase,
and always traveled, dressed, and dined in high style. He loved
military pageantry and was an expert in military history, being
particularly drawn to the ancient military commanders depicted in
the pages of Plutarch's Lives. He relished daring and deplored
cowardice. More than anything else, he loved the thrill, the trial,
and the glory of war, even as he genuinely deplored the deaths of
"so many fine young men" in battle.
Of course, in a modern bureaucratized army serving a democratic
nation, such a classic warrior-type is bound to run into trouble.
In Patton, the general gets in trouble with his nation
for three reasons. 1) He disobeys the intent, if not the letter,
of certain orders, in favor of his own strategically superior plans.
2) He makes controversial statements about foreign policy. 3) He
angrily slaps a soldier admitted to a field hospital with a case
of nerves and calls him a coward. Although Patton gets in a great
deal of trouble with American public opinion over the latter incident,
it is actually a very minor and quite innocent instance of Patton's
deeper problems that threaten to remove him from command at the
height of the war. As in the case of Coriolanus, Patton's defects
are the flip side of his virtues. But unlike Coriolanus, Patton
does not want to rule. He wants only to serve his country as a general.
He wants desperately to do what he seems made for and can do better
than anyone else. Thus, the political issue surrounding Patton involves
whether democracy can make a suitable place for those like him.
That is, does democracy have a place of honor for the warrior, and
more generally, for the man who excels others?
Patton addresses those with vaguely pacifist inclinations who may
be appalled, and in some ways rightly so, by Patton's zest for warfare,
and by the slapping incident particularly. The film also addresses
those inclined to warmly embrace Patton as a Dirty Harry macho-man.
To steer away from both these mistakes, we should focus upon Patton
the thinker, who seeks, not always successfully, to rationally employ
his passion for greatness toward worthy military ends.
All the King's Men
If Patton allows us to see that in a modern democratic society,
military excellence is rather limited in its ability to obtain glory,
let alone power, All the King's Men displays just how much glory
and power can be obtained by political smarts in such a society.
It follows the career of Willie Stark, a character closely based
on Huey P. Long, governor and senator of Louisiana, and, as Harold
Evans puts it in The American Century, "the first
genuine homespun American dictator." Long was immensely popular
with the poor of both races, thoroughly corrupt, and absolutely
ruthless toward his political opponents. Chillingly, he obtained
a great deal of personal control over both the press and the police
of Louisiana, and had he become president, he might have tried similar
tactics on the national stage. America was in the throes of the
Great Depression, and Long began to campaign for president with
an audacious and simple plan of redistributing wealth. Had he not
been assassinated, he may have given FDR a real run for the presidency
in 1936.
Many have seen in Long's rise an instance of American susceptibility
to dictatorship. As Evans puts it:
Long was more of banana republic bully than a Hitler or a Mussolini,
an opportunist rather than an ideologue. But his lightning rise
showed that the institutions of American democracy were vulnerable
to a totalitarian who could identify with the yearnings of the
common people.
Willie Stark is more than simply a fictional substitute for Huey
P. Long, however. All The King's Men was a novel by Robert
Penn Warren before it was a movie, and it has often been hailed
as one of the great American novels, and perhaps the American political
novel. Using Stark and the other main characters of All the
King's Men, we should reflect about the motivations to obtain
and the temptations brought about by political power, especially
the temptation to do political good by using immoral means. We should
also reflect on the egalitarian program of Willie Stark, and the
extent to which it is justified. The film shows the extent to which
the state really had been gripped by a corrupt clique of political
operatives who have neglected the needs of the poor. And when the
disgusted father of the girl killed in the accident objects to Stark's
deeds, he says about Stark's speeches, "The words were good,
still are."
On the other hand, the "yearnings" to which Stark appeals
amount to what Aristotle speaks of in his Politics: the desire
of the poor, because they are more numerous, to divide the property
of the rich among themselves. The man who can exploit this desire,
who can turn the hurt of powerlessness and poverty into a demand
for redistribution, to be accomplished by his own power in the name
of the people, is the classical model of the demagogue, the inevitable
result of the democratic impulse when unrestrained. In All the
King's Men, we see not only the man of boundless ambition against
which Lincoln warned, but the lawlessness of the mob who comes to
stand behind him. The film questions not only Stark's shady means
but the democratic appeal of his rhetoric and political program,
when it shows the envy and ressentiment on which it relies.
While Coriolanus would have had contempt for everything Stark stood
for, he and Stark exhibit a similar desire for preeminence in the
state based upon their own political virtue. For Coriolanus, the
political virtue is courage, for Stark, it is the righteousness
to demand justice for the people, and most importantly, the ability
to obtain it by any means. Thus, All The King's Men allows
us to compare the man of intense ambition in modern democracy to
such a man of earlier times, and also to compare the nature of these
ambitions. One ambition has contempt for the will of the people,
the other ambition seeks to embody it. A key question raised by
All The King's Men is whether a man who seeks to embody
the will of the people mustn't ultimately wind up devouring them
into his own body politic. Many scenes reveal Stark's increasing
control over the citizens of Louisiana, and the main plot shows
how every major character is sucked into Stark's orbit. We see that
not all Stark's utterances are "good," when the film ends
with his dying words, "Could have been--whole world, Willie
Stark."
Bull Durham
The final film selection of our unit looks away from
the world of kings and statesmen, generals and demagogues, to the
world of baseball, which also gives birth to ambition and honors
achievement. This is true even on a minor league team like the Durham
Bulls, most of whose members are well aware that they will never
make it to "the show" (as they refer to the major league),
as they play as much for the love of the game and its challenges
as the paycheck. A new rookie, however, Ebby Calvin LaLoosh, has
a pitching arm that might take him to the majors, but only if the
manager can find a way "to mature the kid." This will
not be an easy job, for although he has "a million dollar arm,"
he seems to have only "a five cents head," and little
control, either over his pitching or his life. For this purpose
the team hires long-time minor league catcher Crash Davis. Contrasting
the two characters, the film shows the growth in both, as they vie
for the attentions of baseball fan and savant Annie Savoy. Annie,
although a community college teacher of literature and composition,
understands her task in life as conveying "life wisdom"
to young ball players, but by the end of the film seems to have
acquired new "life wisdom" herself.
The film raises the question whether baseball is just
a pastime, or even a sport where the ambitious compete and talent
can excel, or whether it is an institution that to at least some
who respect the game can impart the life wisdom that Annie seeks
to convey. At the end of the film, Annie quotes Walt Whitman's prediction
that baseball "will repair our losses and be a blessing to
us." The story of these characters allows us to revisit the
issues of honor and ambitious, self-regard, and even human greatness.
The latter appears in the film in unexpected forms, even in "minor"
leagues. Democratic social conditions are not always and perhaps
even characteristically at odds with human excellence, but make
possible its recognition and even its flourishing.
|